Majestic Law and the Subjective Stop

46 Pages Posted: 27 Apr 2020

See all articles by Kyron Huigens

Kyron Huigens

Yeshiva University - Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Date Written: April 24, 2020

Abstract

Justice John Paul Stevens subscribed to "a majestic conception" of the Constitution. This Article articulates and defends that vision. Majestic law and legal reasoning characteristically involve frank moral reasoning, such as one finds in the Eighth Amendment's "evolving standards of decency" test for proportionate punishment, or in Due Process formulations such as an appeal to "immutable principles of justice, which inhere in the very idea of free government." Majestic law employs moral values, norms, and judgments in legal reasoning, taking them on their own terms. Majestic legal reasoning does not weigh revealed preferences for decency, for example. It asks whether the value of decency is well served.

The principal antagonist to majestic law is the belief that moral values, norms, and judgments are "subjective." That is, these moral commitments are thought to be irrational, arbitrary, prejudicial, mere intuitions, emotional reactions, personal instead of public, or supernatural instead of empirical. This view of moral commitments bars them from use in legal reasoning. In other words, it imposes a "subjective stop." A subjective stop can be a complete bar to moral reasoning in law, but it is more often conditional. A moral value such as "decency" must be reduced to a descriptive form, such as a tally of state sentencing laws, before it can have any bearing on whether a punishment is cruel and unusual under the "evolving standards of decency" standard.

The subjective stop is premised on a mistake. Moral values, norms, and judgments are indeed subjective. It does not follow, however, that these moral commitments are irrational, arbitrary, or in any way unfit for legal reasoning.

The nature and status of moral commitments is the subject matter of metaethics, and the subjectivity of moral commitments is a topic of controversy in metaethics. The subjective stop rests on a primitive emotivism: the view that morality is a set of visceral, "boo" or "hooray" exclamations. This view of morality, however, has no defenders in contemporary metaethics. This Article relies on two alternative subjectivist metaethical theories to defend majestic law and condemn the subjective stop. Allan Gibbard's norm-expressivism explains that, while moral commitments are expressions of emotion, we adjudicate our moral disagreements rationally. To express a moral commitment is to affirm a system of moral norms under which that commitment is rational. A moral norm or judgment is wrong if it is rational only under a system of norms that we cannot rationally accept. Simon Blackburn's quasi-realism starts from the premise that morality is subjective in the most fundamental sense: it is something that human beings project onto the world. Blackburn argues that this changes nothing in what we think or how we act morally. The world onto which we project value imposes limitations on morality, and projection is subject to its own logic, which imposes further constraints. If our moral beliefs are minimally coherent and exhibit epistemic virtues, then they earn the right to be called true. The upshot of both of these theories is a view of moral commitments as subjective, and yet rational and either true or false.

Under these viable subjectivist theories of metaethics, we have no need to reduce moral commitments to descriptive terms before we allow them to operate in legal reasoning. Justice Scalia's insistence that the "evolving standards of decency" test should give way to an inquiry into historical and contemporary practices in punishment rested on a subjective stop - and was mistaken because of it. We can determine what cruel punishment is, and to frame that question in terms of decency is a meaningful and enlightening move. Due Process does not call only for a historical inquiry into past and currently prevailing legal processes in the United States; it also calls for rational inquiry into the truth about "a fair and enlightened system of justice," or "the concept of ordered liberty." To say a handgun is not "critical to leading a life of autonomy, dignity, or political equality," might or might not be true, but it is not enough to say, with Justice Scalia, "Who says?" To say this is to impose a full subjective stop. More importantly, it is, as Justice Stevens argued, an abdication of responsibility that has led to the loss of majestic law.  

Keywords: Constitutional Law, jurisprudence, metaethics, Legal reasoning, Justice Stevens

Suggested Citation

Huigens, Kyron, Majestic Law and the Subjective Stop (April 24, 2020). Seton Hall Law Review, Vol. 51, 2021, Cardozo Legal Studies Research Paper No. 608, Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3584765

Kyron Huigens (Contact Author)

Yeshiva University - Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law ( email )

55 Fifth Ave.
New York, NY 10003
United States
212-790-0404 (Phone)
212-790-0205 (Fax)

HOME PAGE: http://cardozo.yu.edu/directory/kyron-james-huigens

Do you have negative results from your research you’d like to share?

Paper statistics

Downloads
50
Abstract Views
597
PlumX Metrics